This is the second piece in a debate between Dr James Orr and Professor Stephen Hicks. The opening piece James wrote defining Conservative can be found here.
Stephen and James will now write responses to each other’s opening pieces which will be published in due course.
The most direct route to political fundamentals is to ask: What should governments do? The different ‘isms’—liberalism, socialism, fascism, and so on—answer that question based on their most cherished values, holding that the purpose of government is to achieve those values.
Yet societies are complex, and we create many kinds of social institutions—businesses, schools, friendships and families, sports teams, churches/synagogues/mosques/temples, associations dedicated to artistic and scientific pursuits, governments, and so on—to achieve our important values.
So the next question is: What is unique about government, both in terms of what values it is responsible for achieving and how it should do so?
A government is a social institution distinguished by two traits: (1) its principles apply to the whole of society, and (2) they are enacted by physical force or the threat of physical force. That is, governments claim and practice universality and compulsion.
In these two respects government is distinguished from other social institutions, such as businesses, religious associations, sports teams, and so on, which are particular and voluntary. Not everyone in a society does business with a given company, joins a given religious association, plays a given sport, or participates in a given musical group. And when a member of one of those social institutions disagrees with or breaks one of its rules, the most that institution can do is dissociate itself from that member.
A government, by contrast, claims and enacts the authority to apply its rules to everyone in a society. Further, it claims and enacts the authority to use physical force against those who break its rules—confiscation, imprisonment, execution. It is a universal institution of compulsion.
Consequently, the key questions to answer when defining the proper, principled role of government are: What principles are so important that everyone in society should respect and live by them? What principles are so important that physical force may be used against those who violate them?
That is to say, the question of government power requires deep moral thinking.
And that is what puts the various ‘isms’ in conflict with each other, as liberalism, socialism, fascism, and so on, bring to their politics different — often fundamentally different — values, value hierarchies, and philosophical justifications for their values.
The liberal answer to the value questions is, of course, to say that liberty is the top political value. By liberalism I mean the social philosophy that makes foundational the liberty of the individual in all areas of life — artistic, religious, economic, sexual, political, and so on.
Liberalism’s key political claims are that all individuals are entitled to liberty and all individuals should respect each other’s freedoms. That is the universality element. Any individual who violates the liberty of another can properly be subject to physical force. That is the compulsion element. The justification of government’s unique social power is thus based upon the value of liberty.
All other values to be achieved socially, liberalism says, are to be pursued by particular and voluntary institutions. The job of particular businesses is to pursue wealth with those who choose to associate with them. The job of particular religious institutions is to pursue worship with those who choose to so in a similar way. The job of particular sports is to pursue physical challenges with those who choose to participate. The job of musical associations is to pursue aesthetic values with those who choose to be interested. And so on.
Most of society’s work, liberalism thus says, is to be done outside the political sector by particular voluntarily formed institutions. The job of government, by contrast, is to use its uniquely universal and compulsive power in the service of one value: the protection of the liberty of individuals as they pursue their chosen values.
To put it negatively, it is not the task of government to provide any of us with friendships and enriching romantic and family lives, nor with good-paying jobs or spiritual fulfillment, nor with scientific understanding or aesthetically sublime experiences. It is our personal responsibility to seek and create those for ourselves, individually and/or socially as part of voluntary institutions. The task of government is only to provide the liberty-space to do so.
To protect freedoms, liberal governments devise a network of institutional elements. They specify religious liberties, property rights, free-speech rights, liberties to engage in commercial activities, artistic freedom, and more. They set up police, courts, and prisons to investigate those who violate others’ freedoms and to restrain those guilty of doing so.
And, most uniquely among political philosophies, liberal governments place explicit limitations on the scope and power of government itself — especially given the historical lessons of often-terrible abuses of government power — in order to lessen the risk that government itself will violate liberties.
Yet advocates of other political philosophies disagree, and the debate is joined. Is liberty really the most important political value? What about security, prosperity, equality, justice, peace, efficiency, or spiritual purity? Is liberty compatible or in tension with them? In either case, why prioritize liberty?
The radicalism of liberalism is often daunting to its opponents. In part this is because liberalism is a relative newcomer in human history, after millennia of tribalism, feudalism, and many types of authoritarianism. Strong elements of liberalism had short-lived successes in classical Greece and Rome, more recently in some Renaissance Italian and Baltic states, and arguably in a few other places. Only in recent centuries has liberalism become a major contender in theory and practice, and only in some parts of the world.
Further, aside from resistance from traditional forms of politics, liberalism faces formidable opposition from other newcomers such as modern socialisms, fascisms, updated hierarchical authoritarianisms, and systems that try to mix them.
Socialisms and fascisms fundamentally reject liberalism’s prioritizing individuals and instead make a collective the top value, holding that individuals and their assets belong to their preferred collective. Accordingly, they conclude that the government should deploy its universal compulsive power to use individuals and their assets on behalf of the collective.
Hierarchical authoritarians fundamentally reject liberalism’s prioritizing freedom and instead make the possession of power itself the top political value. Or they argue that some individuals are more worthy of power, either due to their differing natural or supernatural endowments and/or their success in the struggle to acquire power. Accordingly, they hold that that the government’s universal compulsive power can and should be used in the service of whatever values its possessors decide.
While all of the ‘isms’ recognize that the government is a uniquely powerful social institution, they differ over the values that justify the government’s use of its unique power. That is to say, politics depends upon more fundamental philosophical beliefs about morality, human nature, and the meaning of life.
Liberalism believes in the individual and in the individual’s fundamental need for freedom to pursue his or her meaning of life. Other ‘isms’ devalue the individual and/or deny the importance of any individual’s need for freedom.
Liberalism has been a robust success in the modern world, yet societies are complex and a few centuries is a brief amount of time in political theorizing, experimenting, and institutionalizing. So liberalism is an ongoing project. It is not against conserving previous generations’ political accomplishments, some of which are now traditions, as long as those accomplishments are justified by their liberty-enhancing effects. And it is committed to ongoing reform or the outright abolishing any still-existing illiberal political traditions.
It is a work in progress.
A completely different side to Mr Orr's article, yet superbly done... there's something in common showing up in both, rearing between the lines of both. I'll wait for the debate to confirm of course...
Quite interesting and provoking
Thanks Konstantin!
And thank you Proff. Hicks
Is conserving liberty, not conservatism. The question is, are you conservatively Liberal or liberally Conservative? Is there such thing as freedom when you should take responsibility for you own values? Well, we can all again there is no freedom being forced to live by other people's values. Well, I can only hope that we all do agree on that one thing.